Demanding Approval: On The Ethics of Alain Badiou
Simon Critchley
What is ethical experience for Alain Badiou? What can be said of the subject
who has this experience? Let me begin by trying to pick out the formal structure
of ethical experience, or what with Dieter Henrich we can call `the grammar of
the concept of moral insight',1 and explaining how such experience implies a
conception of the subject.
Ethical experience begins with the experience of a demand to which I give my
approval. Approval and demand: that is, there can be no sense of
the good - however that is filled out at the level of content, and I am
understanding it merely formally and emptily - without an act of approval or
affirmation. My moral statement that `x is good or bad' is of a different order
to the veridical, epistemological claim that `I am now seated in a chair.' This
is because the moral statement implies an approval of the fact that x is good,
whereas I can be quite indifferent to the chair I am sitting on. If I say, for
example, that it would be good for parrots to receive the right to vote in
elections, then my saying this implies that I approve of this development.
Practical reason is in this way distinct from theoretical reason. In Badiou's
terms, the order of the event (l'événement) is distinct from the order of
being (l'être).
However, if the good only comes into view through approval, it is not good
by virtue of approval. Ethical noesis requires a noema. In
my example, my approval of parrots receiving the right to vote is related to the
fact that - at least in my moral imagination - parrots make a certain demand,
the demand for political representation. Ethical experience is, first and
foremost, the approval of a demand, a demand that demands approval. Ethical
experience has to be circular, although hopefully only virtuously so.
Leaving parrots to one side, in the history of philosophy (and also in the
history of what Badiou calls anti-philosophy, namely religion), this formal
demand is filled out with various contents: the Good beyond Being in Plato,
faith in the resurrected Christ in Paul and Augustine, the fact of reason or the
experience of respect for the moral law in Kant, the certitude of practical
faith as the goal of subjective striving (Streben) in Fichte, the abyssal
intuition of freedom in Schelling, the creature's feeling of absolute
dependency on a creator in Schleiermacher, pity for the suffering of one's
fellow human beings in Rousseau, or for all creatures in Schopenhauer, eternal
return in Nietzsche, the idea in the Kantian sense for Husserl, the call of
conscience in Heidegger, the claim of the non-identical in Adorno, and so on.2
All questions of normativity and value, whether universalistic (as in Kant in
the categorical imperative, and his latter-day heirs like Rawls and Habermas) or
relativistic (as in Wittgenstein on rule following and his latter day heirs like
Rorty), follow from such an experience. Without some experience of a demand -
that is, without some experience of a relation to the otherness of a demand of
some sort - to which I am prepared to bind myself, to commit myself, the
business of morality would not get started. There would be no motivation
to the good, the good would not have the power to move the will to act. Kant
calls that which would produce the power to act, the motivational power to be
disposed to the good, `the philosopher's stone'. What is essential to ethical
experience is that the subject of the demand assents to that demand, agrees to
finding it good, binds itself to that good and shapes its subjectivity in
relation to that good. A demand meets with an approval. The subject who approves
shapes itself in accordance with that demand. All questions of value begin
here.
Let me take this a little further. If we stay with the example of Kant, then
this dimension of ethical experience or moral insight - the capacity of being
motivated to the good - resolves itself, in a rather complex fashion, in the
seemingly contradictory notion of the fact of reason. That is, there is a
Faktum which places a demand on the subject and to which the subject
assents. There is a demand of the good to which the subject assents, and this
demand has an immediate apodictic certainty that is analogous to the
binding power of an empirical fact (Tatsache). The difference between the
apodicticity of a fact of reason as distinct from an empirical fact is that the
demand of the former is only evident in so far as the subject approves it. It
is, if you like (and Kant wouldn't), the fiction of a fact constituted
through an act of approval. However things may stand with the doctrine of the
fact of reason, Dieter Henrich argues, rightly I think, that the entire rational
universality of the categorical imperative and Kantian moral theory follows from
this experience of moral insight. The philosopher's stone would consist
precisely in the link between the motivational power of the fact of reason and
the rational universality of the categorical imperative. Now, because Kant's
entire moral theory is based on the principle of autonomy, the fact of reason
has to correspond to the will of the subject. The fact of reason is a fact, it
is the otherness of a demand, but it has to correspond to the subject's
autonomy. Hence, for Kant, the ethical subject has to be apriori equal to
the demand that is placed on it.
It is arguably this structure that Heidegger repeats in his analysis of
conscience in Being and Time, where conscience is constituted in the
experience of a demand or appeal that seems to come from outside Dasein,
but which is really only Dasein calling to itself. Heidegger writes, `In
conscience Dasein calls itself.'3 In this sense, the grammar of moral
insight in Heidegger, at least in the analysis of authenticity, would be an
existential deepening of Kantian autonomy. Heidegger recognizes as a `positive
necessity' the Faktum that has to be presupposed in any analysis of
Dasein. The Kantian fact of reason here becomes the ontic-existential
testimony, attestation or witnessing (Zeugnis) of conscience which is
relativistically translated into the key notion of the `situation'.4
We can see already, from this little sketch of Kant and Heidegger, that the
claim about ethical experience being constituted in a demand which I approve is
also a claim about the nature of the self or subject. The response to the
question of ethical experience entails a response to the question of the subject
of that experience. The self is something that shapes itself through its
relation to whatever is determined as its good, whether that is the law of
Moses, the resurrected Christ, the suffering other, the intuition of freedom,
the call of conscience, the non-identical, or whatever. If the demand of the
good requires the approval of that demand, then that approval is given by a
self. An ethical subject can be defined as a self relating itself approvingly to
the demand of the good. For me, the ethical subject is the name for the
way the self relates itself bindingly to the good.
This claim about the entailment between ethical experience and the subject
can be buttressed by claiming not simply - and rather neutrally - that the
demand of the good requires approval by a self in order to be experienced as a
demand, but by asserting that this demand of the good founds the self, or
is the fundamental organizing principle of the subject's articulation. What we
think of as a self is fundamentally an ethical subject, a self that is
constituted in a certain relation to a good. This is perhaps best proved
negatively through the experience of failure, betrayal, or evil. Namely, as
Badiou notes, that if I act in such a way that I know to be evil then I am
acting in a manner destructive of the self that I am, or that I have chosen to
be. I have failed myself or betrayed myself. Once again, such a claim is quite
formal and does not presuppose specific content for the good. For example, my
good could be permanent revolution, perpetual peace or paedophilia. This is why
Plato is perfectly consequent when he claims that vice is destructive of self.
Anyone, who has tried - and failed - to cure themselves of some sort of
addiction, whether cigarettes, alcohol, permanent revolution or whatever, will
understand what is meant here. The subject that I have chosen to be enters into
conflict with the self that I am, producing a divided experience of self as
self-failure and the concomitant overwhelming affect of guilt. Guilt is the
affect that produces a certain splitting or division in the subject, which is
something that St Paul understood rather well, `For the good that I would I do
not: but the evil which I would not, that I do.'5
|